Please E-mail suggested additions, comments and/or corrections to Kent@MoreLaw.Com.

Help support the publication of case reports on MoreLaw

Date: 12-15-2015

Case Style: State Of Connecticut v. Santiago

Case Number: SC17413

Judge: Dennis G. Eveleigh

Court: Supreme Court of Connecticut

Plaintiff's Attorney: Timothy J. Sugrue, Terrence D. Mariani, Jr., Maureen Platt

Defendant's Attorney: Katherine C. Essington

Description: Vengeance has no place in the orderly administration of justice by a civilized society. It certainly can never serve as the justification for the death penalty in today's world. My review of the text and legislative history of the public act under consideration, No. 12-5 of the 2012 Public Acts (P.A. 12-5), leads me to the inescapable conclusion that vengeance was the motivating factor underlying the enactment of the provisions allowing the eleven men on death row to be executed while eliminating the death penalty for crimes committed in the future. Because I conclude that there is no longer any valid penological purpose justifying the retention of the death penalty for prerepeal defendants, and that our capital sentencing statutory scheme no longer guards against arbitrariness, it necessarily follows that the portions of P.A. 12-5 that allow the men on death row to be executed are violative of the federal and state constitutional bans against cruel and unusual punishment. See U.S. Const., amend. VIII; Conn. Const., art. I, §§ 8, 9.1 I therefore join the majority's analysis in all respects, and join in remanding the case with direction to sentence the defendant, Eduardo Santiago, to a term of life imprisonment without the possibility of release. I write separately to express my view that, although our state constitution provides separate and distinct protections to the citizens of Connecticut and appropriately prohibits capital punishment, the protections afforded by the eighth amendment to the United States constitution and existing federal case law would have been sufficient to prohibit capital punishment in the state of Connecticut. Moreover, although I agree with the majority that capital punishment is unconstitutional and that the majority properly reached the issue of unconstitutionality, in view of the dissents' claims about the appropriateness of the majority's reaching the issue, I conclude that the unconstitutional aspects of the act could have been severed in order to effectuate the legislature's clear intent to repeal the death penalty. Historically, Connecticut has been a leader in recognizing limits to the application of the death penalty.2 The death penalty is an especially brutal, archaic punishment, and one that has been kept alive only because of our society's acceptance of the traditional theories of punishment, namely, retribution and deterrence. Because the concept of retributive justice inextricably links the severity of a punishment with the culpability of the offender, the death penalty must be available for similarly culpable offenders in order for a capital sentencing scheme to fulfill a valid retributive purpose. By maintaining the death penalty for those who have committed a capital offense before the act's arbitrary effective date while eliminating the death penalty for Page 2any crime committed thereafter, no matter how heinous that crime may be, P.A. 12-5 severs the tie between the imposition of the death penalty and the culpability of the individual offender.IP.A. 12-5 RENDERS CONNECTICUT'S CAPITALPUNISHMENT STATUTORY SCHEMEUNCONSTITUTIONAL UNDER THEEIGHTH AMENDMENT TO THEUNITED STATESCONSTITUTION The eighth amendment to the constitution of the United States bans the infliction of all cruel and unusual punishments. See footnote 1 of this concurring opinion. In assessing the contours of the eighth amendment in the context of the death penalty, the United States Supreme Court has recognized that "the penalty of death differs from all other forms of criminal punishment, not in degree but in kind." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) Solem v. Helm, 463 U.S. 277, 289, 103 S. Ct. 3001, 77 L. Ed. 2d 637 (1983), quoting Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238, 306, 92 S. Ct. 2726, 33 L. Ed. 2d 346 (1972) (Stewart, J., concurring). When a particular type of punishment is challenged categorically or, in other words, when it is argued that a given penalty is never appropriate for a specific category of offender, "[t]he [c]ourt first considers objective indicia of society's standards, as expressed in legislative enactments and state practice to determine whether there is a national consensus against the sentencing practice at issue. . . . Next, guided by the standards elaborated by controlling precedents and by the [c]ourt's own understanding and interpretation of the [e]ighth [a]mendment's text, history, meaning, and purpose . . . the [c]ourt must determine in the exercise of its own independent judgment whether the punishment in question violates the [c]onstitution." (Citations omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) Graham v. Florida, 560 U.S. 48, 61, 130 S. Ct. 2011, 176 L. Ed. 2d 825 (2010). The Supreme Court also has recognized that, because of its ultimate and irrevocable effect, the death penalty cannot be imposed under procedures that create a substantial risk of its infliction in an arbitrary and capricious manner. See Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153, 188, 96 S. Ct. 2909, 49 L. Ed. 2d 859 (1976). Simply put, "[t]he [e]ighth and [f]ourteenth [a]mendments cannot tolerate the infliction of a sentence of death under legal systems that permit this unique penalty to be . . . wantonly and . . . freakishly imposed." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) Id., quoting Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 310 (Stewart, J., concurring). Following our legislature's prospective repeal of the death penalty, the single most determinative factor in Page 3whether a death penalty is imposed or carried out under our capital sentencing scheme is the date on which a defendant commits his or her crime—specifically, whether a defendant has committed his or her crime before April 25, 2012. As I explain in part I A of this concurring opinion, I conclude that, as amended by P.A. 12-5, Connecticut's capital sentencing scheme is contrary to the consensus against executions postrepeal of the death penalty. In addition, as I explain in part I B of this concurring opinion, to allow such an arbitrary factor, which lacks any connection to the purported purposes of the death penalty and the nature of the offenses committed, to have such an extreme impact on the ultimate fate of a limited class of individual defendants is the paradigm of capriciousness that the eighth amendment will not tolerate.AExecuting the Defendant Following the Repeal of theDeath Penalty Is Inconsistent with ContemporaryStandards of Decency Under the test reserved for categorical challenges to the death penalty for a particular class of offender, the first step is to consider objective indicia of society's standards. Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 61-62. In the present case, this step requires the court to examine the standards expressed by legislatures and courts regarding the imposition of the death penalty following a prospective repeal. Although "[t]he clearest and most reliable objective evidence of contemporary values is the legislation enacted by the country's legislatures"; (internal quotation marks omitted) id., 62, quoting Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 312, 122 S. Ct. 2242, 153 L. Ed. 2d 335 (2002); "[t]here are measures of consensus other than legislation. . . . Actual sentencing practices are an important part of the [c]ourt's inquiry into consensus." (Citation omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) Graham v. Florida, supra, 62; accord Kennedy v. Louisiana, 554 U.S. 407, 433-34, 128 S. Ct. 2641, 171 L. Ed. 2d 525 (2008); Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 573, 125 S. Ct. 1183, 161 L. Ed. 2d 1 (2005); Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 316; Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.S. 815, 821-29, 108 S. Ct. 2687, 101 L. Ed. 2d 702 (1988); Enmund v. Florida, 458 U.S. 782, 794-96, 102 S. Ct. 3368, 73 L. Ed. 2d 1140 (1982). On the basis of not only the actions of legislative and executive branches worldwide regarding prospective repeals of the death penalty, but also the actual sentencing practices of other jurisdictions during periods of time in which the death penalty has been repealed, I would conclude that current societal standards unequivocally indicate an unwillingness to impose the death penalty on defendants who committed their crimes prior to the repeal.1Federal and State Case Law Page 4 Although the United States Supreme Court has repeatedly upheld the facial validity of the death penalty; see Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 187; in recent years, that court has limited the situations in which capital punishment is permissible. See Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 413 (death penalty impermissible for nonhomicide crimes against individuals); Roper v. Simmons, supra, 543 U.S. 568 (death penalty impermissible for defendants who committed their crimes prior to age of eighteen); Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 321 (death penalty impermissible for defendants whose intellectual functioning is in low range). That court, however, has never decided whether a state may carry out executions while a prospective repeal of the death penalty is in effect. Nonetheless, this nation's highest court has considered the significance of a prospective repeal of the death penalty for purposes of eighth amendment analysis. In Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 314-15, the United States Supreme Court determined that a national consensus existed against the execution of mentally disabled defendants, relying in part on the fact that eighteen of the thirty-eight states that permitted capital punishment had enacted legislation forbidding the execution of such individuals. See id., 342 (Scalia, J., dissenting). The court was well aware that, of those eighteen states, only seven had prohibited all such executions, while eleven had enacted statutes prospectively prohibiting the execution of mentally disabled individuals, thus maintaining death sentences for mentally disabled individuals who had committed capital offenses prior to the enactment of the repeals. See id., 342-43 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (arguing against inclusion of prospective repeal states). The court declined, however, to draw any analytic distinction between states that had completely abolished the execution of mentally disabled individuals and states that had only had prospectively prohibited it in determining whether a national consensus against the practice had emerged. Id., 314-16. Under Atkins, therefore, a prospective appeal of the death penalty signals a jurisdiction's own consensus against the death penalty.3 Applying the proper standard, I turn now to the practices of our sister states, as articulated by their legislatures and courts. As I explain in further detail subsequently in this opinion, twenty-seven other states and the District of Columbia have, at least at some point in history, eliminated their death penalty, and no executions have been carried out by those states as long as the repeal or invalidation remained in effect.4 Eleven states other than Connecticut, namely, Hawaii, Illinois, Iowa, Maine, Maryland, Michigan, Minnesota, New Jersey, New Mexico, Vermont, and Wisconsin, have enacted repeals of the death penalty that are prospective only in nature.5 Only one state other than Con- Page 5necticut, New Mexico, continues to have individuals sentenced to death despite the enactment of a prospective repeal. See 2009 N.M. Laws 141. The appellate courts of that state have not yet ruled on the constitutionality of the prospective only nature of their repeal, and no executions have been carried out since its enactment.6 Significantly, however, a small number of states have enacted prospective repeals of the death penalty for certain classes of offenders or prospective repeals of procedures that had made a death sentence more likely. In these states, courts consistently have concluded that the repeal must be applied to persons previously sentenced to death.7 I begin with the case law from those states that have addressed the question that is before this court in the context of a partial repeal of the death penalty or death penalty provisions. This case law shows that, like the view taken by the United States Supreme Court, a prospective repeal of the death penalty is deemed to signify consensus that the execution of individuals who fall within the category of offender affected by the prospective repeal, including those individuals sentenced to death prior to the repeal, would violate contemporary standards of decency. See Fleming v. Zant, 259 Ga. 687, 690, 386 S.E.2d 339 (1989), superseded by statute as stated in Turpin v. Hill, 269 Ga. 302, 303-304, 498 S.E.2d 52 (1998); Saylor v. Indiana, 808 N.E.2d 646, 650 (Ind. 2004); Cooper v. State, 540 N.E.2d 1216, 1220-21 (Ind. 1989); State v. Bey, 112 N.J. 45, 51, 548 A.2d 846 (1988); Van Tran v. State, 66 S.W.3d 790, 801-804 (Tenn. 2001). Thus, courts have vacated a defendant's death sentence when, due to prospective changes in that state's capital punishment scheme, the defendant would not have been eligible for the death penalty had he been sentenced after the statutory changes were made. In Cooper v. State, supra, 540 N.E.2d 1220, the Indiana Supreme Court concluded that a prospective repeal of the death penalty for offenders under the age of sixteen rendered the prerepeal death sentence of a fifteen year old defendant unconstitutional under that state's constitution. In considering the Indiana legislature's decision to apply the repeal prospectively despite the fifteen year old defendant's pending death sentence, the court noted: "The bill's sponsors declared openly that this exclusion was purposeful. Although the exclusion [of the defendant] was assaulted on the [h]ouse floor during consideration of the bill as being unjust, it was apparent that the authors wished to enact a general policy without the passion that legislating on a particular case would arouse." (Footnotes omitted.) Id., 1219. The Indiana Supreme Court reasoned as follows in holding that executing the defendant would violate the state constitution:8 "While this case has been pending on appeal, the legal landscape surrounding it has changed dramatically in ways that reflect on the appropriateness of this Page 6death penalty 'in light of other death penalty cases.' " Id. Although the legislature purposefully had crafted the repeal so as not to affect the defendant's death sentence, the court did not find the effective date provision of the act dispositive of the issue of whether it was constitutional to execute the defendant. Id. Rather, the court stated: "Now that Indiana law establishes [sixteen] as the minimum age for the imposition of the death penalty, [the defendant] would be both the first and the last person ever to be executed in Indiana for a crime committed at the age of [fifteen]. This makes her sentence unique and disproportionate to any other sentence for the same crime." Id., 1219-20. This language, in my view, suggests that the court determined that the prospective repeal signified a societal consensus against the execution of any offender who was younger than sixteen years of age at the time of his or her crime, regardless of whether the crime was committed prior to the effective date of the repeal. More recently, in Saylor v. Indiana, supra, 808 N.E.2d 651, the Indiana Supreme Court reduced a death sentence after a change in the law altered the way that the death penalty could be imposed in future cases. The defendant in Saylor had been sentenced to death in 1992, despite a unanimous jury recommendation to the contrary, under a law that allowed the trial judge to override a jury recommendation against death if the trial judge found that the statutory aggravating circumstances outweighed any mitigating circumstances. Id., 647-48. After the defendant's sentence was affirmed, the Indiana legislature enacted legislation that eliminated the trial judge's authority to impose a death sentence in contravention of a jury's recommendation. Id., 648. The defendant thereafter sought rehearing on the judgment affirming his sentence, claiming, inter alia, that his death sentence should be invalidated because, if his sentencing had occurred after the amendments to the capital sentencing statute took effect, he would not have been eligible for the death penalty. Id. On rehearing, the Indiana Supreme Court agreed with the defendant and reduced his sentence from death to a term of years. Id., 651. As it did in Cooper, the court reaffirmed its goal of ensuring " 'evenhanded operation of the death penalty statute' by reviewing death sentences 'in light of other death penalty cases.' " Id., 650. Although the court noted that it had previously affirmed the defendant's death sentence, it explained: "Since that time the legal landscape has significantly changed. . . . [A]s a matter of Indiana state law [the defendant], if tried today, could not be sentenced to death without a jury recommendation that death be imposed. Under these circumstances we conclude that his death sentence is inappropriate and should be revised." Id. The court compared the case before it with its previous decision in Cooper, and stated that both cases presented "situations in which the legislature, after [the defen- Page 7dants'] sentences were imposed, enacted significant changes in the requirements for the death penalty that would render [the defendants] ineligible for a death sentence in a trial conducted today. . . . [W]e conclude it is not appropriate to carry out a death sentence that was the product of a procedure that has since been revised in an important aspect that renders the defendant ineligible for the death penalty." (Emphasis added.) Id., 650-51. Accordingly, the Indiana Supreme Court converted the sentence of death to a term of imprisonment. Similarly, in Van Tran v. State, supra, 66 S.W.3d 792, the Tennessee Supreme Court concluded that it would violate that state's constitutional ban on cruel and unusual punishment to execute a mentally disabled defendant after the enactment of laws prospectively banning such executions. That court concluded that, although the legislature did not intend for the repeal to apply retroactively to those mentally disabled defendants who had been sentenced to death prior to the effective date of the repeal; id., 798-99; the prospective ban nevertheless reflected an "evolving societal view" in that state that executing a mentally disabled individual would violate "contemporary standards of decency." Id., 801-805. The Georgia Supreme Court reached the same conclusion when faced with a challenge to a statute prospectively repealing the death penalty for mentally disabled individuals. See Fleming v. Zant, supra, 259 Ga. 690. That court concluded that the prospective repeal signified that the contemporary " 'standard[s] of decency' " in that state no longer supported the execution of those individuals, including those who were on death row prior to the effective date of the repeal. Id. In analyzing the significance of the prospective repeal, the court stated: "The legislative enactment reflects a decision by the people of Georgia that the execution of mentally [disabled] offenders makes no measurable contribution to acceptable goals of punishment. Thus, although there may be no 'national consensus' against executing the mentally [disabled], this state's consensus is clear."9 (Footnote omitted.) Id. Likewise, in State v. Bey, supra, 112 N.J. 51, the New Jersey Supreme Court gave retroactive effect to a statute prospectively repealing the death penalty for crimes committed by minors. Although in that case the court premised its decision to apply the statute retroactively on rules of statutory construction; id., 100-105; it noted that, apart from the legislature's intent concerning retroactivity, "notions of fundamental fairness . . . would likewise demand retroactive application of the juvenile-offender exemption in this case. . . . Indeed, the [state] . . . concedes that sound public policy and fundamental fairness dictate that [the] defendant not be singled out to be the only juvenile ever executed or Page 8even eligible for execution under our current death penalty law." (Citation omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) Id., 104-105. It is all but a certainty that at least some future offenders protected by the prospective repeal will have the same characteristics as the prerepeal defendants, and that their crimes will be similar to—if not worse than—those committed by the prerepeal defendants, yet only the prerepeal defendants would face the possibility of dying at the hands of the state. As I explain more fully in part I A 3 of this concurring opinion, first, it would be irrational to conclude that the prerepeal defendants may be executed when the legislature has determined that the death penalty should not be available for all future offenders, irrespective of whether their moral culpability is similar to, or greater than, that of the prerepeal defendants. Second, these decisions from our sister states were not all solely grounded on the fact that the legislative enactments addressed offenders who, in general, are less culpable than the average adult offender, and that this diminished culpability rendered imposition of the death penalty unconstitutional. Rather, these decisions aptly highlighted the fundamental unfairness inherent in executing a defendant when, due to a legislative enactment either prospectively repealing the death penalty or substantially altering the way in which the death penalty may be imposed in the future, that defendant would not have been eligible for the death penalty if he or she had been sentenced after the enactment took effect.10 Thus, these courts were also concerned with ensuring the evenhanded operation of their capital sentencing statutes, and viewed the date of an offense as an arbitrary eligibility factor for the death penalty.11 See Saylor v. Indiana, supra, 808 N.E.2d 650; Cooper v. State, supra, 540 N.E.2d 1219; State v. Bey, supra, 112 N.J. 104-105. Thus, the precedents of our sister states, in my view, weigh strongly against carrying out an execution after the legislature has prospectively repealed the death penalty.2Actual Practices in Other Jurisdictions Moreover, in assessing whether a punishment is constitutionally sound, "it also is appropriate for us to consider what is occurring in actual practice." State v. Rizzo, 303 Conn. 71, 191, 31 A.3d 1094 (2011), cert. denied, U.S. , 133 S. Ct. 133, 184 L. Ed. 2d 64 (2012). Thus, in determining whether there is a national consensus against conducting executions while a death penalty repeal is in place, it is proper to look to the number of executions that have occurred in other states while a repeal of the death penalty has been in effect. See Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 63-64 (reviewing statistics concerning number of juvenile nonhomicide offenders serving sentences of life imprisonment without possibility of parole); Kennedy v. Loui- Page 9siana, supra, 554 U.S. 433-34 (reviewing statistics about number of executions of child rapists to determine if such punishment is socially unacceptable); State v. Rizzo, supra, 191-93 (reviewing number of people on death row and number of executions carried out nationally to constitutionality of death penalty). Upon review, it does not appear that any state has ever executed an inmate while a death penalty repeal has been in force.12 Aside from the two states with expressly prospective death penalty repeals, Connecticut and New Mexico; see footnote 6 of this concurring opinion; seventeen states, as well as the District of Columbia, do not have statutes that currently authorize the death penalty. See Death Penalty Information Center, "States With and Without the Death Penalty," (2015), available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/ states-and-without-death-penalty (last visited August 10, 2015). In two of these states—North Dakota and West Virginia—the legislation repealing the death penalty expressly stated that the repeal applied retroactively.13 In six of these states—Hawaii, Illinois, Iowa, Maryland, Minnesota and New Jersey—the death sentences of the remaining inmates on death row were commuted by the executive branch, either before or after the legislature repealed the death penalty.14 In two other states—Massachusetts and New York—as well as the District of Columbia, a court invalidated the existing death penalty statutory scheme, which effectively banned future executions in the absence of a statutory change.15 No such changes have been made. Thus, no postrepeal executions have taken place in the nineteen other jurisdictions which currently prohibit the death penalty. In addition, the following thirteen states have, at various times in our nation's history, temporarily repealed and later reinstated the death penalty, yet none of these states ever executed a person previously sentenced to death while the temporary repeal remained in effect: Arizona,16 Colorado,17 Delaware,18 Iowa,19 Kansas,20 Maine,21 Missouri,22 New Mexico,23 New York,24 Oregon—twice,25 South Dakota,26 Tennessee,27 and Washington.28 No state has executed an inmate while a repeal was in effect.29 Rather, any executions occurred after the death penalty was reinstated and a new death sentence was imposed under the new capital sentencing statute. On several occasions, the sentences of prerepeal death row inmates were commuted to life imprisonment through applicable procedures.30 In other instances, the repeal legislation either expressly31 or impliedly32 applied retroactively.33 The utter absence of postrepeal executions leads me inexorably to the conclusion that there is a national consensus against the practice. In fact, the statistics in this case are far more convincing than some of the statistics relied upon by the United States Supreme Page 10Court in determining that a national consensus exists against a given sentencing practice. See Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 64-65 (concluding that there was national consensus against sentencing juvenile nonhomicide offenders to life imprisonment without possibility of parole when only 123 such people were serving that sentence in eleven jurisdictions); Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 316 (concluding national consensus against executing intellectually disabled defendants existed where five such offenders had been executed in thirteen year period); Enmund v. Florida, supra, 458 U.S. 794 (concluding that society had rejected death penalty for nontriggerman felony murderers where only six such offenders had been executed between 1954 and 1982). Thus, although the United States Supreme Court has determined that a national consensus exists against the sentencing practices in those cases, despite the fact that those sentences had actually been imposed, there cannot be a clearer indicator of consensus than that demonstrated by the statistics in the present case, namely, a complete unwillingness on the part of this nation to impose or carry out a death sentence while a death penalty repeal—either prospectively or in toto—is in effect. The actual practice of these states is the controlling factor, and the practice of these states is, clearly, not to execute. See Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 316 (national consensus exists against executing mentally disabled individuals when, among others things, even states that authorized practice had not actually carried out such executions).3International Considerations Finally, I would point out that, not only is there a national consensus against the imposition of the death penalty while a repeal is in effect, there is a demonstrable global consensus that postrepeal executions are impermissible. According to a recent report by the United Nations, as of 2008, ninety-five countries have abolished the death penalty for all crimes.34 U.N. Secretary-General, "Capital Punishment and Implementation of the Safeguards Guaranteeing Protection of the Rights of Those Facing the Death Penalty; Report of the Secretary-General," (2009), p. 7, available at http://www.crin.org/docs/UN_CP.pdf (last visited August 10, 2015). According to available data, none of these countries have ever executed an individual after the death penalty was repealed, regardless of whether the repeal was accomplished via legislation, executive action, or a determination by a court of law. Id., pp. 60-62; see also Death Penalty Information Center, "Abolitionist and Retentionist Countries," (2015), available at http://www.deathpenaltyinfo.org/abolitionist-and-reten-tionist-countries (last visited August 10, 2015). Thus, if Connecticut were to execute the defendant Page 11after the enactment of P.A. 12-5, it would apparently earn the dubious distinction of becoming the first sovereign entity to execute one of its citizens while a repeal of the death penalty remains in force. In doing so, our state would distinguish itself from a host of countries that have refused to tread the path on which our state now travels, including countries as varied as Argentina, Belgium, Cambodia, Djibouti, France, Haiti, Ireland, Kyrgyzstan, Mexico, Mozambique, the Philippines, Romania, Rwanda, Samoa, Senegal, Serbia, South Africa, Turkey, and the United Kingdom. U.N. Secretary-General, supra, pp. 60-62. In light of the foregoing, I am persuaded that there are clear objective indicia of societal standards supporting the proposition that there is a consensus that the imposition of a sentence of death following a legislative repeal of the death penalty violates contemporary standards of decency.BEnactment of P.A. 12-5 Eliminates Any ValidPenological Objective for Maintaining theDeath Penalty for Prerepeal Offendersfor Reasons Unrelated toTheir Culpability "Community consensus, while entitled to great weight, is not itself determinative of whether a punishment is cruel and unusual." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 67. "In accordance with the constitutional design, the task of interpreting the [e]ighth [a]mendment remains our responsibility. . . . The judicial exercise of independent judgment requires consideration of the culpability of the offenders at issue in light of their crimes and characteristics, along with the severity of the punishment in question. . . . In this inquiry the [c]ourt also considers whether the challenged sentencing practice serves legitimate penological goals." (Citations omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) Id. In Roper v. Simmons, supra, 543 U.S. 568-71, Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 67-71, and Miller v. Alabama, U.S. , 132 S. Ct. 2455, 2465-69, 183 L. Ed. 2d 407 (2012), the United States Supreme Court contrasted the characteristics of juveniles and adults who committed the same criminal behavior, and concluded that juveniles were less culpable than adults who commit the same crime and, therefore, the punishment at issue—whether it was life without parole or the death penalty—would be cruel and unusual if imposed on a juvenile even though the same sentence would not violate the eighth amendment when imposed on an adult. In Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 317-18, the court engaged in a similar analysis regarding adults with intellectual disabilities. In cases such as Coker v. Georgia, 433 U.S. 584, 592, Page 1297 S. Ct. 2861, 53 L. Ed. 2d 982 (1977) (plurality opinion), Enmund v. Florida, supra, 458 U.S. 787, and Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 438-39, the Supreme Court examined whether imposition of the death penalty for a nonhomicide crime violated the eighth amendment. In each case, the court concluded that the imposition of the death penalty would be unconstitutionally disproportionate to the culpability of the offender. See, e.g., Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 438. In reaching its conclusion, the court examined not only societal consensus regarding the punishment faced by the defendant and the underlying penological justifications, but also the characteristics of the crime and the offender. The present case raises an issue that has not been answered by any of the previously cited cases. The defendant asks us to decide whether the imposition of the death penalty would be disproportionate in relation to the particular type of homicide of which he was convicted as to violate the eighth amendment now that our legislature has determined that, moving forward, the death penalty is an impermissible punishment for any offender who commits the same type of homicide. This is fundamentally a different question than the ones posed by Enmund, Kennedy, Coker, Simmons, Atkins, Graham, and Miller. In each of those cases, the court was essentially being asked to make an exception—to spare a group of offenders from an otherwise acceptable penalty. By contrast, in the present case, we are faced with the situation in which Connecticut has determined that the death penalty is no longer an acceptable punishment for any crime committed today. Thus, the question is not whether Connecticut may create an exception to an otherwise acceptable punishment, but whether Connecticut may inflict an otherwise unacceptable punishment on the defendant. An exploration of P.A. 12-5 and how it would impact offenders such as the defendant helps put the question before us in proper context. Public Act 12-5, § 2, amended General Statutes § 53a-35a, effective April 25, 2012. That statute presently provides in relevant part: "For any felony committed on or after July 1, 1981, the sentence of imprisonment shall be a definite sentence and, unless the section of the general statutes that defines or provides the penalty for the crime specifically provides otherwise, the term shall be fixed by the court as follows: (1) (A) For a capital felony committed prior to April 25, 2012, under the provisions of section 53a-54b in effect prior to April 25, 2012, a term of life imprisonment without the possibility of release unless a sentence of death is imposed in accordance with section 53a-46a, or (B) for the class A felony of murder with special circumstances committed on or after April 25, 2012, under the provisions of section 53a-54b in effect on or after April 25, 2012, a term of life imprisonment without the possibility of release . . . ." General Statutes § 53a-35a. The most significant feature of this Page 13scheme for purposes of this part of my analysis is that the conduct classified as a "capital felony" or a "murder with special circumstances" is exactly the same. The legislature simply substituted the term "murder with special circumstances" for "capital felony" in the provision setting forth the eight offenses that were previously eligible for capital punishment. Compare General Statutes (Rev. to 1999) § 53a-54b ("[a] person is guilty of a capital felony who is convicted of . . . [2] murder committed by a defendant who is hired to commit the same for pecuniary gain or murder committed by one who is hired by the defendant to commit the same for pecuniary gain"), with General Statutes (Rev. to 2013) § 53a-54b ("[a] person is guilty of murder with special circumstances who is convicted of any of the following . . . [2] murder committed by a defendant who is hired to commit the same for pecuniary gain or murder committed by one who is hired by the defendant to commit the same for pecuniary gain"). Only the former version of the statute, however, permits punishment by death. Thus, the precise conduct which gave rise to the defendant's capital felony conviction is now defined as "murder with special circumstances . . . ." If the defendant had engaged in identical conduct after April 25, 2012, the death penalty simply would not have been an available punishment. Therefore, the date of the offense, rather than the particular culpability of the offender, is determinative of whether the death penalty is available. With this perspective in mind, I turn to the question of whether such a dichotomy can be justified. Under the eighth amendment, in order for a punishment to pass constitutional muster, it must fulfill a valid penological objective. "Criminal punishment can have different goals, and choosing among them is within a legislature's discretion." Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 71. The two penological justifications traditionally and consistently articulated in support of the death penalty are deterrence of capital crimes and retribution. See Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 441. Unless the imposition of the death penalty "measurably contributes to one or both of these goals, it is nothing more than the purposeless and needless imposition of pain and suffering, and hence an unconstitutional punishment." (Emphasis added; internal quotation marks omitted.) Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 319. Although this court has previously concluded that the death penalty validly serves one or both of these objectives; see State v. Rizzo, supra, 303 Conn. 197-98; it is plain to me that, in light of the prospective repeal, the execution of prerepeal death row inmates no longer measurably contributes to a valid penological objective. There has been a long running debate as to whether the death penalty actually functions as a deterrent to those crimes deemed capital offenses. See, e.g., J. Acker, "Be Careful What You Ask For: Lessons From New York's Recent Experience With Capital Punish- Page 14ment," 32 Vt. L. Rev. 683, 702-11 (2008). Courts have concluded that "[t]he value of capital punishment as a deterrent of crime is a complex factual issue the resolution of which properly rests with the legislatures, which can evaluate the results of statistical studies in terms of their own local conditions and with a flexibility of approach that is not available to the courts." Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 186; see also State v. Rizzo, supra, 303 Conn. 197. Thus, courts have deferred to a legislative judgment that "the possible penalty of death may well enter into the cold calculus that precedes the decision to act." Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 186. Deferring to our legislature is not proper in the present case. Public Act 12-5 eliminates the possibility that any future murderer will be sentenced to death. The potential infliction of the penalty of death, therefore, will no longer enter into an individual's decision of whether to commit murder with special circumstances. Thus, "[f]ollowing the abolition of the death penalty for all future offenses committed in Connecticut . . . it is possible to determine the exact number of potential crimes that will be deterred by executing the defendant in this case. That number is zero." (Emphasis in original.) State v. Santiago, 305 Conn. 101, 321, 49 A.3d 566 (2012) (Harper, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). Accordingly, the execution of the defendant, as well as the executions of the other inmates who remain on death row, cannot be justified by its deterrent effect.35 See Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 319-20 (concluding that executing mentally retarded will not further goal of deterrence). Courts have always treated death differently from other types of punishments in determining what is constitutionally permissible. See Solem v. Helm, supra, 463 U.S. 289; Bullington v. Missouri, 451 U.S. 430, 445-46, 101 S. Ct. 1852, 68 L. Ed. 2d 270 (1981); Beck v. Alabama, 447 U.S. 625, 637-38, 100 S. Ct. 2382, 65 L. Ed. 2d 392 (1980); Gardner v. Florida, 430 U.S. 349, 358-60, 97 S. Ct. 1197, 51 L. Ed. 2d 393 (1977). No court has ever justified the continued imposition of the death penalty on minors or the mentally disabled following repeal because doing so would have promoted stability in the law. The prospective repeal of the death penalty in this statute has eliminated the traditionally articulated rationale of deterring those particularly heinous crimes deemed to justify the punishment of death. Therefore, I turn to the other claimed justification for capital punishment, namely, retribution. Although not a forbidden penological objective, "[r]etribution is no longer the dominant objective of the criminal law . . . ." (Citations omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 183; see also State v. Corchado, 200 Conn. 453, 463, 512 A.2d 183 (1986). The United States Supreme Court has recognized that, of the valid justifications for punishment, Page 15"retribution . . . most often can contradict the law's own ends. This is of particular concern when the [c]ourt interprets the meaning of the [e]ighth [a]mendment in capital cases. When the law punishes by death, it risks its own sudden descent into brutality, transgressing the constitutional commitment to decency and restraint." Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 420. "[T]he heart of the retribution rationale is that a criminal sentence must be directly related to the personal culpability of the criminal offender." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) Graham v. Florida, supra, 560 U.S. 71; see also Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 319 ("[w]ith respect to retribution . . . the severity of the appropriate punishment necessarily depends on the culpability of the offender"). Retribution is committed to general principles mandating similar punishment in similar circumstances. See R. Nozick, Philosophical Explanations (1981) p. 367. Thus, retribution "sets an internal limit to the amount of punishment, according to the seriousness of the wrong . . . ." Id. Retributive justice, therefore, is concerned with imposing a sentence proportionate to the crime, so that the "interest in seeing that the offender gets his 'just deserts' " is satisfied. Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 319; see also Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 442 ("[t]he goal of retribution . . . reflects society's and the victim's interests in seeing that the offender is repaid for the hurt he caused"). Under this theory, it is unjust to create a system that purposefully imposes, or encourages the imposition of, wholly disproportionate punishment on equally culpable defendants. Rather, to fulfill a valid retributive purpose, sentences must be handed out evenhandedly; legislatures and courts cannot simply dole out different punishments, varying not merely in degrees of severity, but in kind, for similar crimes. Indeed, the notion that the death penalty should be reserved for only the most deserving of offenders and, thus, work to produce evenhanded justice, is embedded in this nation's capital punishment jurisprudence. To ensure that only the most culpable of offenders are sentenced to death, the United States Supreme Court has "consistently confined the imposition of the death penalty to a narrow category of the most serious crimes." Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 319; see also Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 442 ("[i]n considering whether retribution is served . . . we have looked to whether . . . the culpability of the prisoner is so serious that the ultimate penalty must be sought and imposed" [internal quotation marks omitted]). The death penalty, therefore, has been reserved for certain crimes "so grievous an affront to humanity that the only adequate response may be the penalty of death." (Emphasis added.) Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 184. In written testimony to the Judiciary Committee, Page 16Chief State's Attorney Kevin Kane acknowledged that "[p]rospective repeal of the death penalty will create two classes of people: one will be subject to execution and the other will not, not because of the nature of the crime or the existence or absence of any aggravating or mitigating factor, but because of the date on which the crime was committed." Conn. Joint Standing Committee Hearings, Judiciary, Pt. 9, 2012 Sess., p. 2937. In so doing, however, our legislature's prospective repeal necessarily establishes that the death penalty is not the only adequate response to those crimes previously deemed capital felonies. What, then, is the real purpose behind executing the men currently on death row, when the legislature has completely taken death off of the table for all crimes committed after April 25, 2012? Although P.A. 12-5 contains no statement of policy or underlying findings, the legislative history establishes two factors that indicate that maintaining the death penalty on the basis of an arbitrary date does not measurably contribute to a valid retributive purpose. First, the various rationales articulated in support of the death penalty's repeal applied to all cases regardless of the date of offense: (1) the death penalty operates in an incurably arbitrary and discriminatory manner;36 (2) the risk of executing an innocent person cannot be eliminated;37 (3) the length of time required for effective appellate and postconviction review would make it more likely that the men on death row would die of old age rather than be executed;38 (4) the death penalty fails to provide closure for victims' families;39 and, of course, (5) moral objections to the state's taking of a life.40 Second, although the legislative debate articulated serious concerns as to the legal and moral propriety of prospective repeal,41 no lawmaker articulated a legitimate or moral rationale for conditioning death upon the date of the offense. The lone comment expressing anything close to such a justification was a suggestion that the state should not upset the expectations of victims' families, a point that I address subsequently in this concurring opinion. See 55 S. Proc., Pt. 3, 2012 Sess., p. 720, remarks of Senator Andrew Roraback. No other legislator indicated that he or she shared that particular view. Rather, it was broadly acknowledged that the decision to repeal the death penalty only on a prospective basis was driven by a desire to exact revenge on certain notorious death row inmates and the fear of the political consequences that could have accompanied an absolute prohibition.42 For example, Representative Lawrence Cafero, an opponent of the prospective nature of the repeal and the abolition of the death penalty generally, stated: "It is no secret that what is weighing over all of us is the [murder of Jennifer Hawke-Petit, Hayley Petit, and Michaela Petit in Cheshire]. In fact, it was widely reported that one of the reasons this General Assembly didn't take this bill up earlier was because of the fresh- Page 17ness of those awful crimes." 55 H.R. Proc., Pt. 3, 2012 Sess., p. 1043; see also 55 H.R. Proc., Pt. 4, 2012 Sess., p. 1063, remarks of Representative Al Adinolfi ("[t]here are many people in this room that have changed in their mind their vote to abolish the death penalty rather than vote against abolishing the death penalty based on these [eleven] who are on death row being executed, especially [Joshua] Komisarjevsky and [Steven] Hayes [who were convicted of capital felonies in connection with the murders in Cheshire]");43 55 H.R. Proc., Pt. 4, 2012 Sess., p. 1305, remarks of Representative Ernest Hewett ("for the members who are voting for a prospective bill so they can make sure that Hayes and Komisarjevsky get the death penalty, it's not going to happen"). Representative Cafero later added that, if the legislature intended to have a debate about the propriety of the death penalty, "let's have that debate. Let's not have this one. Let's not mislead the public. . . . If it is the will of this [c]hamber that this [s]tate is no longer in the business of executing people, then let's say it and do it. You cannot have it both ways." 55 H.R. Proc., Pt. 4, 2012 Sess., p. 1047. Likewise, Representative Themis Klarides, herself a supporter of the death penalty, remarked about the inconsistency inherent in the legislative determination that a select few individuals may be executed, but that execution is unjustified in any circumstance going forward: "I do not get how anybody can say, I believe killing is wrong. . . . What I don't get is, how killing can be wrong for someone else, but [the men currently on death row], they are bad, so we can kill them. . . . You either support the death penalty and taking somebody's life or you don't." Id., p. 1210. These are, obviously, statements selected from an extremely extensive legislative history. Nevertheless, these statements, in my view, accurately reflect the primary reasons behind the prospective nature of the repeal: the desire to see the men currently on death row die, or at least certain of them,44 as well as the avoidance of the political consequences that would have accompanied the abolishment of existing death sentences. Therefore, I can only conclude that the purpose of limiting the repeal of the death penalty prospectively is private vengeance. Private vengeance differs markedly from retribution, and is an impermissible justification for punishment. Whereas retribution is concerned with ensuring that an offender gets his " 'just deserts' "; Atkins v. Virginia, supra, 536 U.S. 319; revenge,45 on the other hand, is personal, or private. A person or society seeking revenge has a personal tie to the victim, or is personally affected by the harm done to the victim. Those seeking revenge are motivated by emotion, and take personal pleasure in the suffering of the offender. See R. Nozick, supra, p. 367. Most significantly, revenge, by its nature, carries no limits on the harm that may be imposed on the offender, whereas retribution sets an Page 18internal limit on punishment according to an offender's culpability. See id. Thus, revenge cares not with what comes of other offenders who commit similar crimes, but is concerned only with harming a specific offender.46 The state contends, however, that executing prerepeal death row inmates does serve a valid retributive purpose because, by carrying out existing death sentences, the state will fulfill promises it has made to the victims of these crimes and, particularly, their families. I cannot agree. Although the office of the state's attorney may have the ability to promise a victim's family that it will seek a sentence of death, it cannot legitimately promise that the offender will be put to death for numerous reasons. The jury may decide not to convict or not to impose a sentence of death. Should the jury vote to impose that punishment, the defendant's death sentence may be vacated on direct appeal, as in the present case, or in collateral proceedings even years later. The board of parole and pardons could commute the death sentence. See General Statutes § 54-124a (d). More fundamentally, selectively executing the men currently on death row in order to fulfill such promises would amount to nothing more than exacting revenge on behalf of the families of the victims. Simply because society demands a certain punishment does not mean that the state is authorized to carry it out. "The mere fact that the community demands the murderer's life in return for the evil he has done cannot sustain the death penalty, for . . . 'the [e]ighth [a]mendment demands more than that a challenged punishment be acceptable to contemporary society.' " Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 240 (Marshall, J., dissenting). "It is undoubtedly correct that there is a demand for vengeance on the part of many persons in a community against one who is convicted of a particularly offensive act. At times a cry is heard that morality requires vengeance to evidence society's abhorrence of the act. But the [e]ighth [a]mendment is our insulation from our baser selves. The 'cruel and unusual' language limits the avenues through which vengeance can be channeled. Were this not so, the language would be empty and a return to the rack and other tortures would be possible in a given case." (Footnote omitted.) Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 344-45 (Marshall, J., concurring). Thus, society's desire to see the men on death row executed cannot alone legitimize executing the prerepeal defendants in light of the death penalty repeal. See State v. Santiago, supra, 305 Conn. 319 (Harper, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) ("[i]f it is upon . . . rage that the death penalty depends, then that penalty cannot stand"). Indeed, it is wholly inconsistent to justify an execution by our society's moral outrage at the offender's conduct when our state no longer sanctions a sentence of death for any crime Page 19committed today. I therefore conclude that the retention of the death penalty for the men currently on death row, after the legislature has declared that the death penalty is no longer a proper punishment for any murderer going forward, serves no valid penological purpose, and marks this state's "sudden descent into brutality, transgressing the constitutional commitment to decency and restraint."47 Kennedy v. Louisiana, supra, 554 U.S. 420. In light of the foregoing principles, I therefore conclude that the execution of prerepeal death row inmates while a death penalty repeal is in effect does not measurably contribute to a valid retributive purpose. Public Act 12-5 ensures that no murderer will be sentenced to death in the future, irrespective of his or her culpability. Thus, the act completely unravels the thread that links the imposition of the death penalty and the culpability of individual offenders. No longer can death be imposed for crimes virtually identical to, similar to, or even more heinous than the crimes committed by prerepeal death row inmates. By repealing the death penalty going forward, the legislature has made a determination that the internal limit of punishment, or the most appropriate penalty, for even the most egregious of crimes is life imprisonment without the possibility of parole. In other words, the legislature has rejected the notion that death is the only adequate response for even the most culpable of offenders; see Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 184; and, instead, has determined that a sentence of life imprisonment without the possibility of parole will suffice to satisfy the interest in seeing that such an offender gets his just deserts.CApplying the Death Penalty on the Basis of the Date ofthe Offense in Relation to the Effective Dateof P.A. 12-5 is Unconstitutionally Arbitrary It is also my view that, as amended by P.A. 12-5, Connecticut's statutory capital sentencing scheme is unconstitutional because, as currently structured, it suffers from the same inequities that plagued the capital sentencing schemes that were declared unconstitutional by the United States Supreme Court in Furman. See Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 238-40. In Furman, a majority of United States Supreme Court justices each came to the independent conclusion that the penalty of death, as it was then currently administered, was so cruel and unusual as to violate the eighth amendment. Id., 240. Although no justice's reasoning could command a clear majority, by examining the decision in Furman in light of two other cases decided in that time period by the United States Supreme Court, namely, McGautha v. California, 402 U.S. 183, 91 S. Ct. 1454, 28 L. Ed. 2d 711 (1971), and Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 153, one comes to understand that the death penalty is in accord with the eighth amendment Page 20only when it is imposed on the most culpable offenders for the commission of the most grave homicides and, importantly, only when this most extreme punishment is imposed fairly, consistently, and based solely on the individual and unique circumstances of each case. What Connecticut has done, by prospectively repealing the death penalty for all types of homicide that previously were defined as "capital felonies" by §§ 53a-35a and 53a-54b, is to remove any assurance that only the most deserving offenders will be selected by our statutory scheme to receive the death penalty on the basis of their individual circumstances. The United States Supreme Court decision in McGautha reveals the problems that occurred under the older versions of our nation's capital sentencing schemes. In McGautha, two men who had been sentenced to death claimed that "the absence of standards to guide the jury's discretion on the punishment issue is constitutionally intolerable. . . . [The] petitioners contend that to leave the jury completely at large to impose or withhold the death penalty as it sees fit is fundamentally lawless and therefore violates the basic command of the [f]ourteenth [a]mendment that no [s]tate shall deprive a person of his life without due process of law." McGautha v. California, supra, 402 U.S. 196. At that point in time, the United States Supreme Court was unwilling to recognize the unconstitutionality of the outdated sentencing schemes that permitted juries to exercise unchanneled discretion in determining a capital defendant's sentence. See id., 203-208. The United States Supreme Court would reverse course only one year later in Furman. In that case, five justices separately concluded that the death penalty as currently administered was unconstitutional under the eighth and fourteenth amendments. Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 238-40. Justice Stewart's opinion, which focused on the random and arbitrary manner in which the death penalty was imposed, heavily influenced the development of modern capital sentencing schemes. Id., 309-10. More than anything else, Justice Stewart was concerned with the unprincipled manner in which the death penalty was being imposed at the time: "These death sentences are cruel and unusual in the same way that being struck by lightning is cruel and unusual. For, of all the people convicted of . . . murders in 1967 and 1968, many just as reprehensible as these, the petitioners are among a capriciously selected random handful upon whom the sentence of death has in fact been imposed." (Emphasis added; footnote omitted.) Id. Thus, although Justice Stewart did not determine that the death penalty itself is a violation of the eighth amendment; see id., 307-308; one can only conclude that whenever randomness, arbitrariness, or capriciousness exert their influence on the imposition of the death penalty, the eighth and fourteenth amendments of the constitution of the United Page 21States have been violated. The plurality opinion in Gregg serves as a guide to legislatures that wish to continue to constitutionally impose the death penalty. In Gregg, the United States Supreme Court approved of a Georgia capital sentencing statute passed in response to Furman: "The basic concern of Furman centered on those defendants who were being condemned to death capriciously and arbitrarily. Under the procedures before the [c]ourt in that case, sentencing authorities were not directed to give attention to the nature or circumstances of the crime committed or to the character or record of the defendant. Left unguided, juries imposed the death sentence in a way that could only be called freakish. The new Georgia sentencing procedures, by contrast, focus the jury's attention on the particularized nature of the crime and the particularized characteristics of the individual defendant. . . . In this way the jury's discretion is channeled. No longer can a jury wantonly and freakishly impose the death sentence; it is always circumscribed by the legislative guidelines." Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 206-207.48 Public Act 12-5 amends Connecticut's statutory death penalty scheme in a manner that, in my view, runs afoul of the principles expressed in Furman. The United States Supreme Court has repeatedly found that death is different. "There is no question that death as a punishment is unique in its severity and irrevocability." Id., 187; see also Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 305 (Brennan, J., concurring) ("death is an unusually severe and degrading punishment"); Furman v. Georgia, supra, 346 (Marshall, J., concurring) (death is "the ultimate sanction"). It cannot fairly be denied that "death is a punishment different from all other sanctions in kind rather than degree." Woodson v. North Carolina, 428 U.S. 280, 303-304, 96 S. Ct. 2978, 49 L. Ed. 2d 944 (1976). "When a defendant's life is at stake, the [United States Supreme Court] has been particularly sensitive to insure that every safeguard is observed. . . . It is an extreme sanction, suitable to the most extreme of crimes." (Citations omitted; footnote omitted.) Gregg v. Georgia, supra, 428 U.S. 187. Instead of resulting from the unfettered discretion of a jury, as in Furman, the arbitrariness in the present case stems from the effective date provision of the act, which, in effect, renders the date on which a defendant commits his crime an eligibility factor for the death penalty. I fail to see how this scheme, which permits the imposition of the death penalty for a capital felony committed at any time prior to 11:59 p.m. on April 24, 2012, but rejects categorically the imposition of the death penalty for the same conduct or even substantially more heinous acts carried out two minutes later, is in any way distinct from the constitutionally infirm schemes rejected by the United States Supreme Court Page 22in Furman. The circumstances that I describe strike me as exactly the sort of wanton and freakish imposition of the death penalty that runs afoul of the eighth amendment of the United States constitution. See Furman v. Georgia, supra, 408 U.S. 310 (Stewart, J., concurring); Callins v. Collins, 510 U.S. 1141 1152, 114 S. Ct. 1127, 127 L. Ed. 2d 435 (1994) (Blackmun, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari) ("[t]he demands of Furman are met by 'narrowing' the class of death-eligible offenders according to objective, fact-bound characteristics of the defendant or the circumstances of the offense" [emphasis added]). In my view, the understanding that, today, only this subset of criminal offenders—those defendants who committed capital felonies prior to the effective date of P.A. 12-5, regardless of individual culpability—will be subject to this punishment causes an arbitrary, anomalous impact on this subset of criminal offenders and therefore causes Connecticut's capital sentencing scheme as amended by P.A. 12-5 to violate the eighth amendment.IISEVERABILITY OF UNCONSTITUTIONALPARTS OF P.A. 12-5 Having concluded that the execution of prerepeal death row inmates violates the constitutional ban on cruel and unusual punishment, and although the majority opinion decides today that capital punishment is unconstitutional, in view of the dissents' claims about the appropriateness of the majority's reaching the issue, I now examine the effect that this conclusion has on the continued viability of P.A. 12-5. My conclusion as to the constitutionality of the act relates solely to the effective date provision of the act, which is the mechanism by which the death penalty is retained for capital felonies committed before the act and abolished for all identical future crimes.49 The issue, therefore, is whether the unconstitutional provisions are severable from the remainder of the act. I would conclude that they are and, thus, would allow the constitutional portions of the act to stand—namely, those portions that effectuate the repeal of the death penalty. In determining the appropriate remedy when a portion of a statute has been found to be unconstitutional, "[w]e seek to determine what [the legislature] would have intended in light of the [c]ourt's constitutional holding. . . . Thus, [g]uiding the solution is the maxim that this court will strive to interpret a statute so as to sustain its validity . . . and [to] give effect to the intention of the legislature. . . . [In enacting] General Statutes § 1-3 the legislature has shown its intention that there is to be a presumption of separability of the provisions and of the applications of statutes. . . . With regard to the separability of provisions, to overcome Page 23the presumption it must be shown that the portion declared invalid is so mutually connected and dependent on the remainder of the statute as to indicate an intent that they should stand or fall together . . . and this interdependence would warrant a belief that the legislature would not have adopted the remainder of the statute independently of the invalid portion. . . . "[U]pon finding a portion of a statute to be unconstitutional, this court does not ask whether, if the legislature had known about the constitutional flaw at the time of enactment, it might have preferred some other form of legislation over the remaining constitutional portion of the statute, a question that might well engage the court in speculation. Rather, this court asks the much narrower question of whether the legislature, at the time that the statute is invalidated, would prefer the continued operation of the constitutional portion of the statute or the complete invalidation of the statute." (Citations omitted; emphasis omitted; footnote omitted; internal quotation marks omitted.) State v. Bell, 303 Conn. 246, 260-61, 33 A.3d 167 (2011). Moreover, I acknowledge that, "even with the presumption of divisibility, we cannot rewrite a statute and give it an effect altogether different from that sought by the measure viewed as a whole especially where offending portions so affect the dominant aim of the whole statute as to carry [the whole statute] down with them." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) In re Robert H., 199 Conn. 693, 704, 509 A.2d 475 (1986), quoting Railroad Retirement Board v. Alton Railroad Co., 295 U.S. 330, 362, 55 S. Ct. 758, 79 L. Ed. 1468 (1935). In attempting to discern the legislature's intent regarding the severability of a statute, this court generally looks to the level of interdependence between the unoffending language and the unconstitutional language of the statute, and seeks to determine whether, if the unconstitutional portion is excised, the remainder still gives effect to the "dominant aim of the whole statute . . . ." (Internal quotation marks omitted.) In re Robert H., supra, 199 Conn. 704. Thus, the analysis does not involve speculation as to how the legislature would have voted had it been aware of the court's constitutional ruling, but rather whether the language chosen by the legislature renders the statute inseverable. For example, in State v. Menillo, 171 Conn. 141, 368 A.2d 136 (1976), this court examined the severability of language contained in General Statutes (Rev. to 1975) § 53-29, which criminalized behavior intended to induce a miscarriage or abortion of a pregnancy. In an earlier decision concerning the same statute, the court concluded that the entirety of the statute was unconstitutional in light of the decisions of the United States Supreme Court in Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 93 S. Ct. 705, 35 L. Ed. 2d 147 (1973), and Doe v. Bolton, 410 U.S. 179, 93 S. Ct. 739, 35 L. Ed. 2d 201 (1973), which upheld a woman's right to an abortion by medically competent Page 24personnel. See State v. Menillo, 168 Conn. 266, 269, 362 A.2d 962 (1975). The United States Supreme Court subsequently vacated this court's decision holding the statute unconstitutional in its entirety, and concluded that neither its decision in Roe nor Doe mandated the total invalidation of the statute. See Connecticut v. Menillo, 423 U.S. 9, 96 S. Ct. 170, 46 L. Ed. 2d 152 (1975). On remand, this court reconsidered its earlier decision, and sought to determine whether the language of § 5329 could be limited to exclude physicians from its operation, and thus ensure a woman's right to an abortion by medically competent personnel. State v. Menillo, supra, 171 Conn. 145. With the foregoing principles on severability in mind, this court concluded that "[t]he exclusion of physicians from the prohibitions of the statute would in no way destroy its effectiveness as to other classes of persons. The invalid inclusion of physicians is not so mutually related to and intrinsically connected with the remainder of the statute as to indicate that the statute would never have been adopted without the inclusion of physicians." Id., 146. Thus, the court concluded that the presumption of severability was not overcome, and that the legislature intended to criminalize the covered behavior when engaged in by a person who was not a physician. Similarly, in In re Robert H., supra, 199 Conn. 693, this court examined statutory language to discern the legislature's dominant purpose in enacting the statute. The defendants in that case had been adjudicated delinquents and committed to state custody after being charged with sexual assault. Id., 695. At trial, the defendants sought to introduce records from the rape crisis center visited by the victim, but the court granted a motion to quash the subpoena because of General Statutes (Rev. to 1985) § 52-146k, which, inter alia, created a testimonial privilege for communications between a sexual assault counselor and a sexual assault victim. Id., 698. The defendants appealed an order by the trial court quashing a subpoena for records from the rape crisis center visited by the victim based on a determination that information contained therein was privileged. Id., 694-701. Specifically, the defendants claimed that the statutory privilege created by § 52-146k was improperly invoked because other language prevented the identity of the sexual assault counselor from being disclosed in a civil or criminal proceeding; General Statutes (Rev. to 1985) § 52-146k (b); and, thus, the definitional elements necessary to qualify an individual as a "sexual assault counselor," which determine whether the privilege applied under the statute, could not be established because the counselor could not be called to testify at trial. Id., 698-701; General Statutes (Rev. to 1985) § 52-146k (a) (5). On appeal, this court agreed that the statute contained conflicting language, stating, "if the identity of the sexual assault counselor cannot be disclosed under Page 25. . . § 52-146k (b), then it would always be impossible to determine whether the statutory criteria set out in § 52-146k (a) (5) were satisfied with respect to that sexual assault counselor." In re Robert H., supra, 199 Conn. 701. After analyzing the language of the statute, the court concluded that "[t]he obvious intent and the dominant purpose of this statute is to grant a privilege to confidential communications between a sexual assault counselor . . . and a victim." Id., 703. Then, instead of striking down the entire statute, the court determined that the "portion of § 52-146k (b) which prohibits the disclosure of the identity of a sexual assault counselor is separable and independent from the balance of the statute given [the statute's] dominant purpose of creating the privilege . . . ." Id., 704. Accordingly, the court remanded the case to the trial court for a determination of whether the sexual assault counselor who treated the victim satisfied the necessary criteria to claim the testimonial privilege. Id., 704-705. The court similarly directed that the counselor's identity be disclosed to the defendants for purposes of cross-examination concerning her statutory qualifications. Id., 705. Similarly, in State v. Bell, 283 Conn. 748, 784-86, 931 A.2d 198 (2007), this court was tasked with determining whether General Statutes (Rev. to 2007) § 53a-40 (h), violated the sixth amendment. The statutory subsection at issue authorized the trial court to impose a substantially harsher sentence on a defendant if: (1) a jury had determined he qualified as a persistent dangerous felony offender and; (2) the trial court concluded that the public interest would be best served by subjecting the defendant to a harsher sentence. See id., 796. Although in that case, the court did look to the legislative history to determine the actual intent of the legislature in amending the statute at issue; see id., 802-803, 812; the court ultimately concluded that, as worded, the statute did violate the sixth amendment because it authorized a sentence enhancement greater than the maximum sentence authorized by the jury verdict. Id., 803-804. Instead of striking the statute in its entirety, however, the court noted that if a phrase were excised from the statute, it would be rendered constitutional while still keeping with the legislature's dominant purpose behind enacting the statute. See id., 811-12. The court did so even though its separation had the effect of altering the legislature's chosen process required for a persistent dangerous felony offender to receive an enhanced sentence. See id., 811-13. With the foregoing principles in mind, I would conclude that the statute in the present case is separable.50 As in In re Robert H., the statutory language in the present case evinces two separate legislative goals: the prohibition of the death penalty for all crimes committed after the effective date of P.A. 12-5; and the retention of the death sentences of the prerepeal defendants.51 It would be anomalous and alarming to conclude that, Page 26in enacting a statute repealing the death penalty, the legislature was primarily concerned with seeing a handful of men executed. Thus, it is clear to me that the dominant purpose of P.A. 12-5 was to prohibit the death penalty for future crimes. The retention of existing death sentences was incidental to the primary purpose of abolition. Indeed, if the obvious intent of the legislature was to retain the death penalty for prerepeal defendants, then why would the legislature have enacted the statute? Connecticut, after all, already authorized the death penalty prior to P.A. 12-5 and, therefore, legislative inaction would have ensured the retention of existing death sentences. Likewise, it is noteworthy that the abolition of the death penalty will affect all future defendants, an unquantifiable and obviously large number, whereas the portion of P.A. 12-5 retaining the death penalty for crimes committed prior to the effective date will affect only those defendants who have committed capital felonies prior to the effective date. Thus, striking down P.A. 12-5 in its entirety would thwart its primary purpose—the abolition of the death penalty.52 The state claims, however, that an examination of the legislative history of P.A. 12-5 shows that the legislature would not have repealed the death penalty without retaining preexisting death sentences and, therefore, that the statute is not severable. I disagree. In certain instances, when legislative intent is not readily apparent from the plain language of the statute, this court has examined the legislative history of a statute when determining whether a statute is severable. See State v. Bell, supra, 303 Conn. 261-63; State v. Bell, supra, 283 Conn. 802-803. Even if one examines the legislative history of the act, the state's argument lacks merit. This court does not seek to determine whether, if the legislature had known about the constitutional flaw at the time of enactment, it would have enacted the remaining constitutional portion of the statute, an exercise that would engage this court in speculation. See State v. Bell, supra, 303 Conn. 261. Rather, the question this court must answer is whether the legislature, at the time that a portion of the statute is declared unconstitutional, would prefer the continued operation of the constitutional portion of the statute or the complete invalidation of the statute. Id. In answering this question, the court must keep in mind that there is a presumption in favor of severability. See General Statutes § 1-3. Moreover, this court should keep in mind that, if only a portion of a statute is found to be constitutional, it should be severed from the offending remainder "unless this court determines that the legislature would have enacted it in precisely the same form if it had known of the constitutional flaw at the time of enactment." (Emphasis in original.) State v. Bell, supra, 303 Conn. 261 n.12. As this court explained in Bell, this means that this court would have to find that the legislature would not have repealed the death penalty if it had Page 27been aware of the constitutional flaw in P.A. 12-5. See id. Although I consider the dominant purpose of the statute to be evident from its plain language, an examination of the relevant legislative history bolsters my conclusion that the offending portion of the statute is, in fact, severable from the constitutional remainder. Although the state points to select portions of the legislative history that highlight an insistence that the repeal be prospective,53 there is also evidence that many legislators were in favor of a complete repeal of the death penalty. More importantly, the legislature was warned, in no uncertain terms, that an attempt to repeal the death penalty only prospectively was likely to run afoul of both the federal and state constitutions. Consider, for example, a portion of Chief State's Attorney Kevin Kane's testimony before the Judiciary Committee: "If it is passed in this form and it's prospective and a crime occurs the day before it becomes effective my feeling is [that] there's—I know I wouldn't, I know I won't seek the death penalty for a crime that occurs the day before it becomes effective. I think that would be arbitrary. And I wouldn't—just wouldn't plain feel right doing it. That's my opinion."54 (Emphasis added.) Conn. Joint Standing Committee Hearings, Judiciary, Pt. 8, 2012 Sess., p. 2633. Asked point-blank by a legislator "does this law, this bill stop [offenders who committed capital felonies prior to the effective date] from receiving the death penalty?" Id., p. 2646. Chief State's Attorney Kane responded: "the wording of the bill itself does not but my prediction is . . . that as a result of . . . this bill passing people won't be executed whether [they have] been sentenced or not." (Emphasis added.) Id. Similarly, another legislator urged the House of Representatives to adopt an amendment to the bill that became P.A. 12-5 that would have reinstated the death penalty for all offenders if this court were to determine that the repeal of the death penalty was constitutionally required to apply to those currently sentenced to death: "This amendment, Madam Speaker . . . now is very appropriate. There are many people in this room that have changed in their mind their vote to abolish the death penalty rather than vote against abolishing the death penalty based on these [eleven] who are on death row being executed, especially, Komisarjevsky and Hayes . . . . And what I'm saying is that we will be misleading the people in this room that have changed their decision because the death penalty will still stay in place for those that are on death row if we do not pass this . . . amendment . . . we would be doing them a wrong. And I think those people would . . . have been misled by this coming out, because I believe that those who put in this bill, with the prospective in there, know that eventually this is going to go away, and they're misleading the rest of the [r]epresentatives that will be voting here today; therefore, I urge all my colleagues in this room to support this amendment. 55 H.R. Proc., Page 28Pt. 4, 2012 Sess., p. 1063, remarks of Representative Adinolfi. The amendment, which was described by its sponsor, Representative John Hetherington, as "the opposite of a severability clause . . . think of it that way"; id., p. 1061; failed by a vote of fifty-four to eighty-eight, with nine votes not present or abstaining. Id., p. 1066. A matching amendment failed in the Senate. The amendment's sponsor explained the need for it as follows: "[T]he intent is—Senator [Eric] Coleman had indicated that the bill he believes not to be unconstitutional. Therefore this amendment does not have to go forward. And I guess I look at it as a spare tire in your trunk. You may not need it. But if it is unconstitutional, you have it. And you've protected the intent of the [l]egislature, which is not, clearly not to let the [eleven] currently on death row to get a different sentence. And if that's clearly what we want to do this amendment will ensure that takes place. And there's many of us around the [c]ircle who, at least I understand, were debating whether to vote in favor of getting rid of the death penalty or not. But clearly an effort to change their mind was the relief or satisfaction that the [eleven] who are currently on death row would continue to be on death row absent—even with this legislation. All this does is say absolutely true. And if your wishes are not upheld, and if those [eleven] end up with a lesser sentence, which was not our intent, we will do away with getting rid of the death penalty. It's just protection that gets what we all wanted. And if that's a major factor, this is how you protect it." (Emphasis added.) 55 S. Proc., Pt. 3, 2012 Sess., p. 668, remarks of Senator Leonard Fasano. This proposed amendment also failed to pass, receiving fifteen votes in favor and twenty against, with one vote not present or abstaining. Id., p. 669. All of the legislators who voted against this amendment were presumably aware of the statutory presumption codified at § 1-3 in favor of severing invalid provisions from the remaining inoffensive language of a statute at the time that they rejected these amendments. See, e.g., State v. Fernando A., 294 Conn. 1, 21, 981 A.2d 427 (2009) ("the General Assembly is always presumed to know all the existing statutes and the effect that its action or non-action will have upon any one of them" [internal quotation marks omitted]). Further, other legislators plainly believed that there might be constitutional issues associated with a purely prospective repeal: for example, Senator John Kissel stated the following in response to testimony that sought to assure the legislature that a prospective only repeal could be accomplished: "[T]his is Connecticut, this is New England, this is a debate that's not going away any time soon and I really do believe once this step is made, the other shoe's going to fall, inevitably, if not sooner than we all think. And whether it's driven by a Supreme Court decision, appeals, or whether a Page 29future legislature a few years from now says, wow, we can't have [eleven] people on death row and have everybody else—or some horrible, horrific criminal commits a crime and because it's a few days after this goes into effect then the argument is we've got this individual here who can only face life without [the] possibility of release, that is fundamentally unfair to these other individuals and that's—that becomes much more difficult for folks such as myself who are advocates and proponents of the death penalty." Conn. Joint Standing Committee Hearings, Judiciary, Pt. 9, 2012 Sess., p. 2768. Accordingly, I conclude that the portions of P.A. 125 that render it unconstitutional are not so mutually connected to the constitutional remainder so as to indicate a legislative intent that the entire act should fall and that, therefore, the provision of P.A. 12-5 requiring prospective application is severable.

Outcome: The effective date provision of P.A. 12-5 is patently unconstitutional under the federal constitutional ban on cruel and unusual punishment. Moreover, our state constitution's prohibition of excessive and disproportionate punishment renders capital punishment unconstitutional. If our state had executed one person while the prospective repeal is in effect, it would have separated itself from not only all of the states in our own country, but from all of the countries in the modern world. Instead of continuing its tradition as a paradigm for the elimination of the death penalty for certain classes of individuals, Connecticut would have descended into the murky depths of the uncharted waters of death penalty executions postrepeal of the death penalty statute. The majority's decision today derives from the strength of our collective moral ethos. Our laws should never succumb to the inherent indecency associated with a vengeful purpose directed toward a few isolated individuals. I do not believe that this is the legacy which Connecticut wishes to leave to its future generations.

Plaintiff's Experts:

Defendant's Experts:

Comments:



Find a Lawyer

Subject:
City:
State:
 

Find a Case

Subject:
County:
State: